Friday, April 25, 2014

A Colonial Order Framework?


“Referring to concepts such as the liberal order framework and state formation, discuss the rise of the modern state in Canada”

Ian McKay, in “The Liberal Order Framework: A Prospectus for a Reconnaissance of Canadian History” considers liberalism as a means for analyzing the “historically specific project of rule” that formed in Canada. [1] He argues that Canada was “simultaneously an extensive projection of liberal rule and an intensive process of subjectification.”[2] McKay suggests that liberalism be approached from a neo-Marxist framework, using class as a site for analyzing other points of intersection and oppression.[3] However, he notes the presence of histories of women and ethnic minorities, including Indigenous people, suggesting that these “autonomous subaltern histories” can be connected using a “liberal-order ‘bridge” that considers how they have been conceptualized as Others, apart from the liberal project.[4] Liberalism is an important but insufficient framework for understanding the struggles of these “Others” in relation to nation-building processes in Canada. Instead, the colonial element of nation-building must be placed at the forefront as a lens through which to analyze other social and political relations, as an element that underpinned liberalism, which itself took shape on the Canadian stage in conjunction with increasingly nuanced and oppressive ideologies about race and sex. This paper will therefore detail the expansion of a white settler state, premised on a colonial, liberal, patriarchal framework. Such a process was neither totalizing nor uniformly coercive, neither neutral nor inevitable. It appears to have been twofold, entailing the spread of infrastructure and the spread of ideology.
The language used to describe state formation processes is important, as it has the potential to portray state building as hegemonic and naturalized, or contested. To start, “rising” is not an appropriate word to describe state formation, as it implies a sense of inevitability and obscures the violence and power relations behind this process. Instead, state formation was a re-formation, replacing previous structures. “Modern” is a nebulous concept, linked to technology, order, and rationality. It is generally associated with colonial rather than indigenous states and societies. Linked with masculine and colonial power, valuing “modernity” is a rhetorical means of buttressing an order based on white, male rule. For the purposes of this paper, a definition of the state would consider not merely infrastructure, but values, comprising government and its institutions as well as the values that normalized the use of these institutions; it is a contested concept, rather than a stable entity. Defining liberalism is a complex matter, as it is often contradictory and fluid, with many shifting components. Tina Loo’s definition partly encapsulates it by noting the link of liberalism and capitalism; she positions liberalism as “a political philosophy whose emergence in the eighteenth century not only paralleled the growth of capitalism, but shaped and was shaped by it.”  [5] Keith Smith refers to it as “a matrix of flexible formations,” noting that liberalism varies significantly in theory and in practice.[6] While on one level it is a discourse, liberalism also has a visible material impact.[7] Liberalism is thus a prescriptive and hegemonic theory of social organization that conflates self-interest with state interest. Cecilia Morgan notes that “public” is a mutable and gendered concept.[8] For clarity, I am putting “public” in quotation marks to illustrate this contestation, although this is not reliably visible in the historiography. As this paper will show, the notion of “public” is an integral component of state formation, reflecting a complex nexus of liberal and republican values.
McKay defines a liberal order as “one that encourages and seeks to extend across time and space a belief in the epistemological and ontological primacy of the category ‘individual.’” [9] This interweaves in complex ways with the centrality of “public” as a category, as which was derived from a selective subset of individuals, privileged through the formation of classist, racist, and patriarchal norms. McKay situates a “Canadian liberal revolution” in the late nineteenth century.[10] Notably, however, this coincides with the prominence of increasingly republican values such as public education, discourse, space, and order. This collision of values is not, however, incompatible with McKay’s analysis, as he notes that ideological compromises and “bargaining with hegemony” produced a hybrid specific to Canada that enabled the persistence of a liberal order.[11]
McKay argues that Canada is “essentially a liberal empire, not a nation, and not a democratic state.”[12] His use of the word “empire” presents this as an imposition, rather than a project of mutual creation. This provokes a number of questions, taken up in a variety of ways by the historians whose work underpins this paper. For whom, and in what situations, was this a common sense, totalizing philosophy? How cohesive was this project? How hegemonic? The liberal order framework is useful but insufficient for explaining the expansion of the state structure that emerged in Canada, as it acknowledges but does not emphasize the critical role of colonialism. The premise of equality in liberalism is a false premise, of course, when applied in a colonial context. Smith notes this as well, arguing that liberalism was a “means of, and justification for, colonialism.”[13]
The years prior to Confederation, particularly surrounding the Rebellions of 1837 and 1838 in Upper and Lower Canada, were a key period for the formation of processes and institutions of governance. This formation centered on tensions of local and central, or “court” and “country” in framing the relationships and power dynamics of a heterogeneous settler state with complex social and political ties to Britain and the United States. As Gordon Stewart outlines, Canadian state development created a “peculiarly hybrid political culture” drawing from elements of both these nations. [14] A tension between central “court” and local “country” politics transferred from Britain to Canada and informed fledgling political parties. Stewart argues that Canada’s political formation was not a hybrid of “court” and “country” but had a more extreme “court” orientation encoded in the 1791 constitution.[15] “Country,” in this context, was a powerful rhetorical weapon for reformers, as it conjured images of the weaker executive orientation of the United States.[16]
Stewart situates political formation in Canada as taking place primarily from the 1790s to the 1840s; [17] it is, however, notable that this analysis focuses on central Canada, rather than the north and west where the implementation of political processes and infrastructure in a European model took place later. Rather than entering its denouement in the 1840s, political formation continued, albeit on a more diffuse level, through the early twentieth century. Stewart argues that Confederation was a means of giving the government stability, which had been a challenge given the absence of a colonial ruling class;[18] however, state formation in Canada instead rested on the assumption that the ruling class would be colonial, rather than Indigenous. Patronage was a social and political phenomenon that was important for both the government and reformers, as it enabled a rise in party politics and served as a stabilizing force.[19] An attitude of localism, pervasive due to nineteenth century economics, demographics, and communications, became entrenched through patronage,[20] which in turn entrenched and perpetuated a patriarchal colonialist system. Stewart notes that reformers did not aim to reduce executive power but to reduce it, opening participation and patronage to a wider base.[21] While Stewart does not verbalize such an argument, it is possible to derive from his work that patronage stabilized a self-serving system of liberal nation building, premised on patriarchal, colonialist values, in which even reformers resembled the ruling class.
The mechanisms of liberalism and the interplay of local and central state forces are apparent in several studies of Lower Canada. Jack Little argues in State and Society in Transition that law courts were not imposed on the Eastern townships, as its residents desired this infrastructure to resolve civil matters, although they preferred to manage social disorder in their local communities. [22] Little repeatedly emphasizes the “entrenched sense of localism” in the Eastern Townships, where communities desired a municipal system to reduce social and economic isolation but insisted that this be on their own terms.[23] He illustrates this persisting interplay of local and central power in a successive analysis of school acts; ultimately, despite restructuring that produced some extent of centralization, the local school persisted as a vital social institution.[24] In The Patriots and the People, Allan Greer identifies the parish as a site for “local self-management,” positioning parishes as potentially more important than state legal institutions, and partly reflecting the limited reach of the British colonial state in rural areas.[25] Donald Fyson argues that the emergence of a liberal state in Lower Canada was continuous and fluid, rather than occurring through a series of ruptures in French-English relations.[26] Like Little and Greer, he highlights the interplay of local power and central authority, arguing that rural areas did not uniformly reject state legal infrastructure although they preferred local legal independence.[27] Even where the elite implemented a system, it was used more broadly by local people, and was not a direct means of oppression.[28] Legal infrastructure in this area ostensibly served to protect private property and public order.[29]
In Upper Canada, Bruce Curtis outlines an ongoing tension between local and central factors in the administration of education, a struggle that was entangled with the implementation of responsible government, as reformers were concerned that, without responsible government, centralized education would operate as a form of imperialism. [30] Curtis notes that responsible government was a “notoriously vague” concept, with definitions varying between moderates and radicals.[31] From a reformer perspective, responsible government could be a potential counterbalance to the centralized power of the executive.
Jeffrey McNairn approaches state formation from a different standpoint, considering the workings of a “deliberative democracy,” in which the exchange of ideas took place in the public sphere.[32]  Voluntary associations, overwhelmingly male, acted as miniature republics and thus defined the “public.” For instance, Masonic lodges were a site for expressing liberal values, and thus were sites of male reasoning that “embodied the liberalism of the period.”[33] McNairn argues that a “government based on public opinion was a prerequisite for state formation,” yet the state formed along liberal lines, with a “public” opinion that emphasized privacy and individualism.[34] This illustrates a tension between liberalism and republicanism that dovetails yet contrasts with Morgan’s analysis of religion and public life. According to Morgan, “separate spheres” is a powerful yet imperfect conceptual framework, as the public and private spheres were blurred and interdependent, and “the social” was neither binary nor voluntary, but a space infused with power relations.[35] Stewart, similarly, notes that political parties were social institutions as well as political ones.[36]
Curtis’s analysis of the Educational State is particularly illustrative of a potential analysis drawing from the liberal order framework, although, of course, Curtis’s work predated McKay’s by twelve years. Curtis argues that the construction of the Educational State was “accomplished only through the destruction of a prior educational organization and the marginalization of the structure of educational possibilities it presented. Education was certainly not synonymous with state schooling…that we often equate the two today is another accomplishment of this Educational State.”[37] The same could be said for liberalism; as McKay argues, it was not a neutral or inevitable growth, and as Curtis notes, the debate over education reflects a larger debate about the state more broadly.[38] Curtis discusses the social contradiction in creating a system based on compulsion while treating individual subjectivity as a fundamental principle;[39] this seems to be a central paradox of liberalism, emphasizing public discourse and common good alongside private property and individualism. Curtis’s Educational State, like the liberal state more broadly, was a self-serving, paradoxical system.[40]
The extent to which state formation was imposed upon the settler population is a matter of debate in the historiography, notably between Little and Curtis. Little argues that the state did not impose infrastructure on the community. He notes that “state” and “community” were both fluid concepts, focusing on state formation at the local level to consider the role of the community in shaping the state. [41] In the heterogeneous Eastern Townships, a “profound sense of localism” gave state institutions popular legitimacy.[42] Curtis, on the other hand, sees the Educational State as more of an imposition, “part of a conscious state policy.”[43] What these divergent viewpoints miss, however, is the extent to which white settler society was itself an imposition upon an Indigenous population, even an itinerant one.
While this historiography on Upper and Lower Canada is not, excepting Morgan’s work, explicitly focused on gender relations, one can nonetheless see that “state” and “society” are both implicitly gendered male. It is evident that, in Lower Canada, women were not generally perceived as political actors. The “protection” of women through repealing women’s franchise in 1834 positioned women as non-citizens, [44] and women’s political participation could even be a source of ridicule. Little, for example, recounts that for men in the Eastern Townships, women making petitions was a source of amusement rather than a serious political statement.[45] State formation in this era was largely an exclusive rather than an inclusive project, debating the role and configuration of a “responsible government” that was, in any manifestation, largely elite and colonial in its character.
Much of the historiography obscures the “settler” aspect of the Canadian state in debating the nuances of its formation, and the extent to which it was imposed. Even in situations where settlers supported expanding state infrastructure, this was still the expansion of a colonial framework over a land that settlers—and often historians—presumed to be empty and available by discounting Aboriginal people’s land use practices. Some historiography of Upper and Lower Canada neglects to note that Indigenous state structures in this area predated European settlement, an element that significantly complicates any model of a Canadian state.[46]
Nineteenth-century public debate concerning state formation emphasized a need for rationality, which was linked to manliness and whiteness in a way that excluded women and infantilized First Nations people.[47] While the “state” was not necessarily imposed on the “society” in a model where both are conceptualized as largely white, male entities, this situation becomes considerably more complex when foregrounding the colonial elements of state formation. Curtis metaphorically conceptualizes the role of public schools in Upper Canada as “outposts in the moral wilderness” and a civilizing force among the settler population.[48] This usefully highlights one complex role of the expansion of infrastructure in “frontier” areas.
Through an analysis of western and northern parts of Canada, one can see how state formation took place beyond the creation of a particular form of government. In these areas, state structures and values became entrenched through a convergence of liberalism, colonialism, and paternalism, implementing infrastructures that reflected a particular vision and version of modernity. Histories of the law, the environment, and the reorganization of space illustrate how the regulatory elements of the state had uneven impacts and were hegemonic, though not totalizing. This reorganization, premised upon ideas of scientific knowledge, was a means for Europeans to manifest their goal of mastery over the environment, which, in a colonial view, included Indigenous people alongside animals and waterways. [49]
Perry argues that colonial British Columbia illustrates a “specific moment in state formation” entailing, in part, the efforts of a small and diverse settler population to assert their whiteness.[50] This was intensive and expansive though not, as other historians have noted, totalizing or cohesive. Colonial expansion, as Perry shows, operated on many levels: public health initiatives in response to smallpox epidemics served as a means of containing Aboriginal people, banning them from urban spaces.[51] Vital statistics enabled colonial authorities to measure and regulate marriage, which was a means of instituting state values.[52] The family more broadly became a state institution, bolstered by land and immigration laws that shaped the character of colonial society according to constructions of gender, race, and class.[53] Ideologically, these initiatives reflected a belief in the importance of private property — this is apparent in the absence of free land grants and land allocations that prioritized families.[54] The family, it seems, transcended constructions of public and private: it was a public institution to the extent that it embodied state values and was regulated by state infrastructure, yet colonists treated certain family affairs as private matters. For instance, the colonial state was often reluctant to intervene in incidents of spousal violence.[55]
Little and Fyson have both argued that settler society in Quebec and Lower Canada made use of legal infrastructure, on their own terms. This pattern is also apparent in the colonization of British Columbia, where settlers made use of legal courts to enable economic development. [56] Loo situates law as a socially constructed element of a liberal order that was inextricable from the market economy.[57] Liberalism, she argues, naturalized the use of courts as the exclusive venue for rational conflict resolution.[58] As most settler relationships were economic, the law was largely a means of securing property and, thus, social stability.[59]
The use of the law to secure property and social stability was not an uncontested process; the Grouse Creek War, for instance, showed a conflict of local and customary versus colonial and formal law.[60] As Loo argues, “the existence of multiple meanings of law placed limits on its authority.”[61] McKay notes that the liberal order framework often focuses on “individuals” in the abstract,[62] but it is important to remember that the people here not a nebulous force, and ideology is not an agent. The limits of legal authority due to individual decisions are illustrated in the interplay of judge Matthew Begbie’s actions and the “public” response to it. Begbie, in this case, represented a colonial and formal construction of the law, in contrast to the local and customary law represented by miners in a series of legal cases.[63] Among Begbie’s controversial decisions was overriding a jury’s verdict, prompting concern surrounding legal administration in the colony.[64] Underpinning Begbie’s actions was his failure to recognize the law as socially constructed, assuming instead that human behaviour would be universally rational.[65] McNairn refers to the “public man” as a “universal, impartial figure.”[66] The example of Begbie makes it evident that this was a problematic ideal. Legal cases thus show the complexities and contradictions in ideologies that were premised upon abstractions, and the result for non-abstract individuals who were valorized or excluded by them.
McKay suggests using the history of reserves to consider the liberal revolution in Canada, seeing federal policy concerning Aboriginal peoples as “a fulfillment of liberal norms, which required the subordination of alternatives.” [67] In Keith Smith’s analysis of this subject, it becomes apparent that liberalism was “an exclusionary rather than inclusionary force” that enabled the dispossession of Indigenous peoples.[68] Through this dispossession, liberalism stressed the importance not of freedom and equality, but the defense of private property and the individuals who held it.[69] While unevenly applied, liberal paradigms created knowledge to normalize power relations through a web of surveillance and data collection to control Indigenous territories and resources, and the individual mobility of Indigenous people.[70] In a setting where private property was a “public” value, Indigenous people became, to borrow the words of Judith Raftery, “not part of the public.”[71] The textures of this can be seen in greater detail by examining conservation efforts that blended together the interests of business and industry with those of the state and scientists, at the expense of Indigenous Canadians.
Carl Berger has asserted that the organization of science locally, nationally, and internationally resembled the political structures of provincialism and centralization. [72] Natural science and conservation, in this sense, mirrored and interacted with the state, even when it was not as explicitly a component of state formation. In States of Nature, Loo considers the legal regime for wildlife regulation, untangling its ideological influences. Loo shows how Progressivism and scientific management interacted with anti-modern sentiments, informing treatments of wildlife. Private individuals, independent from, yet interacting with, the state, held an important role in conservation efforts.[73] Provincial-federal relations operated in a complex patchwork, reflecting a variety of ideologies and traditions.[74] Conservation shifted from a fragmented and local approach in the late nineteenth century to a scientific, structured intervention in the twentieth century.[75] Efforts to avoid the privatization of wildlife were underpinned by a hidden goal of restricting access to a narrow and privileged “public.”[76] This idea of a restricted “public” also comes through in Loo’s consideration of government initiatives in northern Canada to create a “national commons.” The forcible relocation of Aboriginal people as part of this caribou conservation effort shows the restrictive nature of these “commons.”[77] Loo’s broad study is thus illustrative of the multiple threads linking the histories of the environment and state formation.
Conservation efforts intersected with “modern” infrastructure, in some cases drawing First Nations into a position of dependence. For instance, Matthew Evenden describes how in 1913, at Hell’s Gate in the Fraser River, rockslides triggered by railway construction had a dramatic impact on salmon spawning, prompting scientific debate and efforts to aid the spawning fish. [78] This scientific effort drew, in an incomplete fashion, from Coast Salish knowledge of the area to combine Indigenous methods of manipulating the fish with Euro-Canadian scientific authority. Ultimately, despite their use of Coast Salish knowledge of Hells Gate, scientists echoed a common twentieth century concern of Aboriginal mismanagement of resources, restricting Coast Salish fishing that they believed would undermine efforts to rescue the fish. This had a long-term impact of fish shortages, increasing economic dependence on government aid.[79] Concerning the damming of rivers in what he refers to as “hydraulic imperialism,” Evenden argues that the fish versus power debate was influential for science, with the debate and science shaping one another.[80] The debate gave authority and privileged access to biological knowledge, building a division between experts and amateurs, and requiring approval by scientists for further development. This also shows how a new institutional framework emerged for a bidirectional relationship between politics and science.[81]
John Sandlos links conservation with colonialism and social control, arguing that the federal government claimed authority over natural areas, such as Wood Buffalo National Park, on the premise such areas being “pristine.”[82] The bureaucracy imposed by the state denied First Nations sovereignty over their traditional territories and colonized First Nations knowledge, privileging “modern” colonial structures and land uses.[83] In a colonial interpretation, conservation was a matter of restricting which humans could have access to particular spaces on the premise of science and modernity.[84] State officials emphasized responsibility and rationality in manipulating the landscape, presenting these concepts as a contrast to First Nations practices.[85] Sandlos sees this dispossession as an intentionally integral element of conservation programs, which operated with a conscious goal of denying First Nations sovereignty and changing their lifestyles as a component of domesticating the northern frontier.[86] The dispossession of First Nations peoples of their land rested upon constructed concepts of “waste” and “crisis” that demonized First Nations land uses and engineered a sense of urgency concerning the environment.[87] Conservation was not a benevolent project, but a mechanism of social control and modernization, benefitting commerce, rather than wildlife.[88] Unconvincingly, Sandlos seems to suggest that this system was cohesive, bordering on conspiratorial. This is unlikely, however, partly because the state worked in tandem with other facets of society, enabling the social, cultural, economic, and political wellbeing of white settlers.
Countering Sandlos, Cole Harris notes that state discipline and surveillance were sporadic, not totalizing. Although the state intended itself to be a totalizing project, the violence of reorganizing land was not wholly a state project, with individual settlers also implicated in imposing values and creating social and geographic boundaries.[89] Harris details the formation of a new human geography in British Columbia based on prioritizing private property and agriculture.[90] This land system was also, he argues, a “disciplinary appendage” of the state, underpinned by a range of epistemological and regulatory practices.[91] For example, the census was “an instrument of the growing regulatory power of the modern nation-state” through which the state could subjugate Indigenous peoples in the name of a “modern” project of researching the population.[92] Harris also illustrates the intertwining of modernization and state formation in the compression of distance through transportation and communication technologies.[93] This was, according to Harris, part of a process of de-territorializing and re-territorializing space in a new configuration, and a component of the integration of British Columbia into a modernizing world. It was neither politically nor culturally neutral.[94] In this framing, Harris astutely emphasizes the mutually constitutive role of colonialism and the nation-state in relation to land.
Gordon Stewart has argued that in Canada, business and politics were integral to one another, reflecting a social and economic reach of government unmatched in Britain or the United States. [95] This trend is also apparent in “frontier” areas. Loo notes that the role of the Hudson’s Bay Company in conservation in western Canada preceded government involvement;[96] taken together with her analysis of governance and legal infrastructure under the Hudson’s Bay Company during the fur trade era, it is clear that corporations have been intertwined in processes of state formation. In The Politics of Development, H.V. Nelles similarly considers the relationship between business and the state. He outlines the involvement of the Ontario provincial government in late nineteenth and early twentieth century staples industries, arguing that the province’s business-oriented strategy to development resulted in the Ontario government becoming essentially a business client. Nelles particularly considered how the intersection between politics and business reshaped and potentially undermined principles of responsible government. Involvement with staples resource industries became a test of ministerial accountability, where politicians were forced to balance their business roles as shareholders with their responsibility to constitutional process. This test of ministerial judgment was often less than satisfactory, as the government privileged business interests. Businesses based on staples industries could thus “use the state to stabilize, extend, and legitimize their economic power.”[97] This was particularly evident, Nelles argues, during the Depression, when industrialists gained at the expense of other social groups, eroding the social sense of responsible government.[98] Nelles illustrates how “the public” was closely entwined with “the state” as he discusses how, in the late nineteenth century, a concern about maintaining “public” ownership of hydroelectric resources was equated with state ownership, as a control against the “abuses of capitalism.”[99] In the early twentieth century, despite questioning over the compatibility of business interests and responsible government, this principle of public or state ownership became limited, such that the association between politicians and businessmen made the government responsible to resource industries.[100] Nelles pessimistically concludes that the “politics of development” created a welfare state, in which business were the primary beneficiaries.[101] This corporate involvement was ongoing; Evenden argues that in the 1950s corporate and provincial development goals coalesced, aiming to show Canadian capabilities and an intangible sense of “progress.”[102]
This analysis illustrates how the complexities of liberalism become increasingly complicated when placed in relief with colonialism. State formation in Canada was not cohesive, but likely appeared totalizing to those dispossessed by the expansion of a colonial state, as it was extensive and multi-faceted. If not hegemonic, the liberal and colonial underpinnings of the Canadian state are in a position approaching hegemony. There appears to be a bizarre fusion of liberalism and republicanism in Canadian state formation, in which a “modern” state values a “public” based on liberal values. Gordon Stewart describes Canadian political parties as “political dinosaurs” that cannot cope with twentieth century problems, as their brains are disproportionately small compared to their political weight and presence. [103] The foundations of the Canadian state more broadly are similarly reptilian, fragmented, circular, and paradoxical.




Works Cited


Berger, Carl. Science, God, and Nature in Victorian Canada. The Joanne Goodman Lectures 1982. Toronto; Buffalo: University of Toronto Press, 1983.

Curtis, Bruce. Building the Educational State: Canada West, 1836-1871. Barcombe, Lewes, East Sussex: Falmer Press, 1988.

Fyson, Donald William. Magistrates, Police and People: Everyday Criminal Justice in Quebec and Lower Canada. Toronto: Published for the Osgoode Society for Canadian Legal History by University of Toronto Press, 2006.

Evenden, Matthew D. Fish versus Power: An Environmental History of the Fraser River. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.

Greer, Allan. The Patriots and the People: The Rebellion of 1837 in Rural Lower Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1993.

Harris, Cole. The Resettlement of British Columbia: Essays on Colonialism and Geographical Change. Vancouver, BC: UBC Press, 1997.

Little, J. I. State and Society in Transition: The Politics of Institutional Reform in the Eastern Townships, 1838-1852. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1997.

Loo, Tina Merrill. States of Nature: Conserving Canada’s Wildlife in the Twentieth Century. Nature, History, Society. Vancouver: UBC Press, 2006.

Loo, Tina Merrill. Making Law, Order, and Authority in British Columbia, 1821-1871. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1994.

McKay, Ian. “The Liberal Order Framework: A Prospectus for a Reconnaissance of Canadian History.” Canadian Historical Review 81, no. 4 (December 2000): 617–51.

McNairn, Jeffrey L. The Capacity to Judge: Public Opinion and Deliberative Democracy in Upper Canada, 1791-1854. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000.

Morgan, Cecilia Louise. Public Men and Virtuous Women: The Gendered Languages of Religion and Politics in Upper Canada, 1791-1850. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996.

Nelles, H. V. The Politics of Development: Forests, Mines & Hydro-Electric Power in Ontario, 1849-1941. 2nd ed. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2005.

Perry, Adele. On the Edge of Empire: Gender, Race, and the Making of British Columbia, 1849-1871. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001.

Sandlos, John. Hunters at the Margins: Native People and Wildlife Conservation in the Northwest Territories. UBC Press, 2008.

Smith, Keith D. Liberalism, Surveillances and Resistance: Indigenous Communities in Western Canada, 1877-1927. Edmonton: AU Press, 2009.

Stewart, Gordon T. The Origins of Canadian Politics: A Comparative Approach. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press, 1986.



[1] Ian McKay, “The Liberal Order Framework: A Prospectus for a Reconnaissance of Canadian History,” Canadian Historical Review 81, no. 4 (December 2000): 621.
[2] McKay, 624.
[3] McKay, 631.
[4] McKay, 628.
[5] Tina Merrill Loo, Making Law, Order, and Authority in British Columbia, 1821-1871, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1994), 8, 159.
[6] Keith D. Smith, Liberalism, Surveillances and Resistance: Indigenous Communities in Western Canada, 1877-1927, The West Unbound: Social and Cultural Studies Series (Edmonton: AU Press, 2009), 12.
[7] Smith, 4, 7.
[8] Cecilia Louise Morgan, Public Men and Virtuous Women: The Gendered Languages of Religion and Politics in Upper Canada, 1791-1850, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996), 214.
[9] McKay, 624.
[10] McKay, 635-636.
[11] McKay, 644.
[12] McKay, 645.
[13] Smith, 12.
[14] Gordon T. Stewart, The Origins of Canadian Politics: A Comparative Approach (Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press, 1986), 3.
[15] Stewart, 20-23.
[16] Stewart, 30.
[17] Stewart, 1.
[18] Stewart, 61, 98-99.
[19] Stewart, 67, 90, 92-93.
[20] Stewart, 98.
[21] Stewart, 30.
[22] J. I. Little, State and Society in Transition: The Politics of Institutional Reform in the Eastern Townships, 1838-1852 (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1997), 50.
[23] Little, 169, 170.
[24] Little, 175-185, 237.
[25] Allan Greer, The Patriots and the People: The Rebellion of 1837 in Rural Lower Canada (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1993), 68, 88, 90, 100.
[26] Donald William Fyson, Magistrates, Police and People: Everyday Criminal Justice in Quebec and Lower Canada (Toronto: Osgoode Society for Canadian Legal History, University of Toronto Press, 2006), xiii.
[27] Fyson, 73, 202.
[28] Fyson, 308.
[29] Fyson, 218.
[30] Bruce Curtis, Building the Educational State: Canada West, 1836-1871 (Barcombe, Lewes, East Sussex: Falmer Press, 1988), 45, 84.
[31] Curtis, 51.
[32] Jeffrey L. McNairn, The Capacity to Judge: Public Opinion and Deliberative Democracy in Upper Canada, 1791-1854 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000), 8.
[33] McNairn, 75-82.
[34] McNairn, 212.
[35] Morgan, 10, 182.
[36] Stewart, 57.
[37] Curtis, 15.
[38] McKay, 23.
[39] Curtis, 369.
[40] Curtis, 373.
[41] Little, 7, 12.
[42] Little, 238-239.
[43] Curtis, 45.
[44] Greer, 198, 205-206.
[45] Little, 165.
[46] For a sense of the complexity of Iroquois society, see Daniel K. Richter, The Ordeal of the Longhouse: The Peoples of the Iroquois League in the Era of European Colonization (Chapel Hill: Institute of Early American History and Culture, University of North Carolina Press, 1992), Richard White, The Middle Ground: Indians, Empires, and Republics in the Great Lakes Region, 1650-1815, 20th anniversary ed (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011), and Gail D. MacLeitch, Imperial Entanglements: Iroquois Change and Persistence on the Frontiers of Empire (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2011). Even “settlement” is problematic terminology; Adele Perry argues that this “depoliticizes the process whereby white people came to dominate First Nations territory” (Adele Perry, On the Edge of Empire: Gender, Race, and the Making of British Columbia, 1849-1871 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001), 7). “Settler” here should be considered as shorthand for settler-colonists, to acknowledge that this was a colonial process with significant underlying power relations, even if the people involved did not necessarily perceive their experiences in that fashion.
[47] McNairn, 219, 226.
[48] Curtis, 370.
[49] The term “frontier” here serves as shorthand for regions somewhat removed from urban areas in central Canada where the white settler state was implemented somewhat later. This is not, however, a neutral term. See, for example, Phillip Deloria, “What is the Middle Ground, Anyway?” The William and Mary Quarterly 63(1).
[50] Adele Perry, On the Edge of Empire: Gender, Race, and the Making of British Columbia, 1849-1871 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001), 6, 14.
[51] Perry, 111.
[52] Perry, 99.
[53] Perry, 125.
[54] Perry, 127, 129.
[55] Perry, 173.
[56] Loo, Making Law, 71.
[57] Loo, Making Law, 3, 52-53.
[58] Loo, Making Law, 75, 89.
[59] Loo, Making Law, 92.
[60] Loo, Making Law, 114.
[61] Loo, Making Law, 114.
[62] McKay, 626.
[63] Loo, Making Law, 114-115.
[64] Loo, Making Law, 116-117.
[65] Loo, Making Law, 131.
[66] Loo, Making Law, 232.
[67] McKay, 640.
[68] Smith, 2.
[69] Smith, 15.
[70] Smith, 94, 131.
[71] Judith Raftery, Not Part of the Public: Non-Indigenous Policies and Practices and the Health of Indigenous South Australians 1836-1973 (Kent Town, South Australia: Wakefield Press, 2006).
[72] Carl Berger, Science, God, and Nature in Victorian Canada, The Joanne Goodman Lectures 1982 (Toronto; Buffalo: University of Toronto Press, 1983), 27.
[73] Tina Merrill Loo, States of Nature: Conserving Canada’s Wildlife in the Twentieth Century, Nature, History, Society (Vancouver: UBC Press, 2006), xvi.
[74] Loo, States of Nature, xvi.
[75] Loo, States of Nature, 6.
[76] Loo, States of Nature, 40.
[77] Loo, States of Nature, 136.
[78] Matthew D Evenden, Fish versus Power: An Environmental History of the Fraser River (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 19.
[79] Evenden, 42.
[80] Evenden, 79.
[81] Evenden, 232, 264.
[82] John Sandlos, Hunters at the Margins: Native People and Wildlife Conservation in the Northwest Territories. (UBC Press, 2008), 13, xix, 24.
[83] Sandlos, 45.
[84] Sandlos, 55, 76-77.
[85] Sandlos, 84.
[86] Sandlos, 139.
[87] Sandlos, 151-152, 196.
[88] Sandlos, 230, 233, 241.
[89] Cole Harris, The Resettlement of British Columbia: Essays on Colonialism and Geographical Change (Vancouver, BC: UBC Press, 1997), 46, 65-68.
[90] Harris, 90.
[91] Harris, 101.
[92] Harris, 137.
[93] Harris, 193.
[94] Harris, 253, 162.
[95] Stewart, 84-85.
[96] Loo, States of Nature, 94.
[97] H. V. Nelles, The Politics of Development: Forests, Mines & Hydro-Electric Power in Ontario, 1849-1941, 2nd ed, (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2005), 427.
[98] Nelles, 487.
[99] Nelles, 306.
[100] Nelles, 382-383, 428.
[101] Nelles, 492.
[102] Evenden, 205.
[103] Stewart, 100.

No comments:

Post a Comment